�������� IT
842: ALTERNATIVE SYSTEMS OF PROBABILISTIC REASONING
����������������������������������������������� ����� FALL 2007
����������������������������������� ���� INSTRUCTOR: DAVE SCHUM
THE BASIC SUBJECT MATTER OF THIS
COURSE:
����������� In this seminar we will examine
alternative views of the process of drawing conclusions from masses of
incomplete, inconclusive, ambiguous, dissonant, and unreliable evidence. Among
the views we will discuss are the Bayesian,
Baconian, Shafer-Dempster, and Fuzzy
systems for probabilistic reasoning. Each one of these formal systems, as well
as others to be mentioned, has interesting properties that deserve our
attention. The necessity for considering alternative views seems evident since
it seems far too much to expect that any one formal system of probability can
capture all of the richness of probabilistic reasoning. We will examine grounds
for the necessity of considering alternative views of probabilistic reasoning
and, in the process, consider applications of each of these views to
non-trivial inference problems. Of particular interest to us are issues
concerning what seems to constitute "rational" probabilistic
reasoning.
����������� A
survey of alternative formal systems of probabilistic reasoning, by itself, is
not quite enough to provide an adequate background for later applications. Many
other issues arise in the application of any of these formal systems. Some of
these issues concern the fact that most human inference problems seem to
involve mixtures of the tasks of
inductive, deductive, and what has been termed "abductive" reasoning.
One very important issue concerns the discovery
or generation of the essential ingredients of probabilistic inference:
hypotheses/possibilities, evidence, and arguments providing the linkage between
evidence and hypotheses. Such generation is an exercise in imaginative,
creative, or abductive reasoning [the essential topic of IT 944]. Another
important issue concerns the coupling of probabilistic reasoning and choice. In
some contexts [science, for example] probabilistic reasoning has a life of its
own. In many other contexts, however, such reasoning is embedded in the further
process of choice in which difficult value-related issues arise. We will also
examine various contemporary views about the coupling of probabilities and and
values in the process of choice.
TEXTUAL AND OTHER REFERENCES ON
PROBABILISTIC REASONING:
����������� 1).
There are many relevant and interesting works on the topic of probabilistic
reasoning to be found in a variety of disciplines; our lives are simply too
short to master all of them. One trouble is that most published works on the
topic of probabilistic reasoning do not provide much discussion of the very
basis for it, namely evidence.
Many of the works we will consider focus just upon algorithms for combining probabilistic
judgments of various sorts and say very little about the evidential foundations
for such judgments. After offering this seminar for a number of years, and at
the suggestion of many students who completed it, I decided to write a book
that covers what I regard as the basic evidential foundations of each of the
formal systems of probability we will discuss. This book is entitled: The Evidential Foundations of Probabilistic
Reasoning� [Northwestern University
Press, Evanston, IL. 2001; paperback edition]. Some of the chapters of this
book are based upon notes I gave students in previous offerings of this course.
In addition, four former students provided editorial and other comments on this
work to ensure that its contents would be especially relevant to the interests
of PhD students in IT and in other areas at GMU.
����������� 2).
There are, of course, many other references to consider; these references come
from many different disciplines and frequently involve matters about which
there is not widespread awareness. At the end of this syllabus is a
"seed" bibliography containing some basic references that are keyed
to the major probability systems we will discuss in this seminar.
����������� 3).
During this seminar I will provide you with an assortment of notes and handouts
on particular topics. In most cases these notes will consist of applications of
the various probabilistic reasoning systems and additional sensitivity analyses
of the sort you will find in the text noted in 1) above.
TOPICS AND READING ASSIGNMENTS
����������� Following
is the sequence of topics we will cover in this seminar together with
associated reading assignments from: Evidential
Foundations of Probabilistic Reasoning [EFPR]. The dates shown are only
approximate; we may wish to dwell longer on some topics than on others.
I. SOME PRELIMINARY MATTERS
[30 August]
����������� To
set the stage for later discussions, I will begin by giving you a bit of
history of the development of interest in the evidential foundations of
probabilistic reasoning. In the process I will try to convince you that any
theory of probabilistic reasoning must be concerned about two major issues: (i)
structural matters in the generation of arguments from evidence to
hypotheses/possibilities, and (ii) matters concerning the assessment and combination
of ingredients associated with the force, strength, or weight of evidence on
these hypotheses/possibilities. Further, I will elaborate a bit on my claim
that human reasoning in natural settings [the "real world", if you
like] involves mixtures of the three forms of reasoning I mentioned above. I
will also give you an overview of the literature that exists in so many
disciplines that is relevant to an understanding of the complexity of
probabilistic reasoning.
II. EVIDENCE, PROBABILITY,
AND STRUCTURAL ISSUES [6 - 13 September].
����������� When
most people think about probability they think only about numbers. But,
as I will explain, probability theories are equally concerned about the arguments
that are constructed to support the use of numbers. The construction of
arguments is a creative task concerning which most of us have very little
appropriate tutoring. This is especially true when we must construct arguments
from masses of evidence. We will consider some exercises showing just
how difficult this can be. One major benefit of studying structural matters is
that it allows us to discern various recurrent forms and combinations of
evidence and to observe how evidence is used during the process of
probabilistic reasoning, regardless of the view of probability one adopts. To
be useful in probabilistic reasoning, evidence must have certain credentials
concerning its relevance, credibility, and inferential force,
strength, or weight. No evidence comes to us with these credentials already
established; they must be established by cogent arguments. The major issue that
divides the alternative views of probabilistic reasoning we will examine
involves how best to grade the inferential force, strength, or weight of
evidence and then to combine such gradations across many items of evidence.
����������� Reading
Assignment: EFPR Chapters 1 - 3.
III. STRUCTURAL ISSUES AND
COMPLEX INFERENCE [20 -27 September]
����������� There
is presently a substantial level of research on what are called inference
networks. In a wide variety of applied areas, people have the difficult
task of trying to make sense out of masses of evidence that, upon examination,
reveal all of the forms and combinations of evidence we will have considered in
Section II. When arguments are constructed from a mass of evidence they begin
to resemble complex networks. Many [not all] of the important elements of
complex inference can be captured in graph theoretical terms. Naturally, there
are many current attempts to develop various forms of computer assistance in
coping with the complexity of inference based on masses of evidence. Matters we
discuss here will be quite relevant to other courses now offered in IT&E
concerning inference networks [e.g. Professor Kathy Laskey's course on Bayesian
networks].
����������� Reading
Assignment: EFPR Chapter 4
IV. ALTERNATIVE PROBABILITY
SYSTEMS I: BASIC THEORETICAL ELEMENTS �
���� [4 October - 8 November]
����������� Here
we come to a discussion of the different views about probabilistic reasoning.
If only for historical reasons, we begin with the conventional, Pascalian, or
Bayesian system for probabilistic reasoning. Then we will consider the
Shafer-Dempster theory of belief functions, Cohen's system of Baconian
probability for eliminative� and
variative induction, and Zadeh's ideas on fuzzy reasoning and fuzzy probabilities.
Our basic objective here is to examine what one is committed to when one
applies any of these formal systems. A question frequently asked is: which one
of these systems do you prefer? This is rather like asking whether you prefer
your saw or your hammer. Each system "resonates" to particular
important elements of probabilistic reasoning. Each system has something
important to tell us about probabilistic reasoning, but no system says all
there is to be said. At this point we will dwell upon what is meant by the term
"rational" probabilistic reasoning. In this section we will also give
attention to the matter of combining probabilistic and value-related judgments
in situations in which probabilistic reasoning is embedded in the further
process of choice.
����������� Reading
Assignment: EFPR Chapters 5 - 6
V. ALTERNATIVE PROBABILITY
SYSTEMS II: EXAMPLES AND APPLICATIONS
����������� ��� [15 - 22 November].�
����������� Having
examined the theoretical underpinnings of alternative systems of probabilistic
reasoning, we will examine what each produces in applications in different
inferential contexts in which different forms and combinations of evidence are
encountered. In some cases, our examination will consist of sensitivity
analyses performed on probabilistic expressions designed to capture various
forms and combinations of evidence. It is in this process that we begin to
observe how many important and interesting evidential and inferential
subtleties lie just below the surface of even the "simplest" of
probabilistic reasoning tasks. These subtleties, if recognized, can be
exploited in our probabilistic reasoning.
����������� Reading
Assignment: EFPR Chapters 7 - 8
VI.
DISCOVERING THE INGREDIENTS OF PROBABILISTIC REASONING [29 November - 6 ������� Dec.]
����������� As
I noted, the ingredients of probabilistic reasoning are rarely provided for us
[except in classroom exercises and examples]; they have to be discovered or
generated. Stated in other words, there is the necessity for imaginative or
creative reasoning in every probabilistic reasoning task. What we only have
time to do is simply to examine some of the imaginative elements of
probabilistic reasoning. The topics of discovery and imaginative reasoning are
of sufficient importance that we devote an entire seminar to the topic [IT 944]
that is offered in the Spring semester.
����������� Reading
Assignment: EFPR Chapters 9-10
PROCEDURAL MATTERS AND METHOD OF
EVALUATION
����������� To
tell you how I believe this seminar should proceed, I will make reference to
the thoughts of Sir Francis Bacon. Bacon argued that, in any scholarly
activity, reading makes us full,
discourse makes us ready, and
writing makes us accurate. We will
all do a fair amount of each in this seminar. As far as reading is concerned, you have one major text and the various
handouts and other materials I will give you. In addition, the reference list I
include at the end of this syllabus contains a wealth of information on all of
the probability systems we will discuss. You can pick and choose among these
references depending upon where your interests take you.
����������� As
far as discourse is concerned, I
look upon this seminar as an experience in the sharing of ideas. Indeed, my
view of scholarship is that it is a sophisticated form of sharing; we learn
from each other. I have no wish to monopolize our discussions. On each occasion
we meet I will try to get things started and will bring various matters to your
attention. What happens after this depends upon you. Often, you may believe I
am saying outrageous things with which you disagree; if so, your task is then
to show me how I have been misled. In addition, you may have questions that I
have not raised; your task is to raise them as we proceed. In short, I hope our
meetings will be both enjoyable and productive; whether or not this happens
depends upon all of us.��
����������� Finally,
the topic of writing brings us to
the first of two methods of evaluating your progress in this seminar. We will
encounter literature from a number of different disciplines; no one discipline
dominates scholarship on probabilistic reasoning. Together, the various works
we will discuss supply a breadth of view. Depth of view is provided by your
focus upon one or more of the formal systems; such focus will form the basis
for a paper you will write, which will count 75% of your grade. The choice
of focus is yours, provided that it concerns probabilistic reasoning or some matter that directly involves such
reasoning. Here are some characteristics of your written work that I will look
for. Notice that I here mention several criteria that will also be in force as
far as your dissertation is concerned.
����������� (1)
Your work should demonstrate that you have attempted to apply your own thoughts
to the issues/problems that you address. A simple review of literature on some
topic [e.g. X says this, Y says that] will not suffice. What you think about the issues your paper
addresses is what is of primary importance. I do not insert this criterion out
of perversity; it is the most important criterion that will be applied in
evaluating your doctoral research.
����������� (2)
Your written work should, of course, demonstrate awareness of the relevant work
of others. When you discuss previous work on your chosen topic, you should give
evidence of having integrated it in a careful and sensible way and are suitably
critical of ideas you encounter. Unless you do these things, I will not be able
to judge how you drew the conclusions you did from the work of others. This
also happens to be a criterion that will be enforced in your doctoral
dissertation.
����������� (3)
Perhaps many of you are now engaged in outside work to which the essential
ideas in this seminar are relevant. In the past I have been quite free in
allowing students to report on their efforts to apply ideas from this seminar
to some ongoing project of interest in their outside work. Sadly, only a small
number of these papers have been of a level of quality one expects from
doctoral students. One reason is that students frequently spend too much time
dwelling upon institutional issues in the problem domain and too little time on
the theoretical probabilistic matters that are being applied in this domain. In
some cases there was very little evidence in a paper that the student actually
mastered any probabilistic matters that could have potential application. I
certainly hope and expect that there will be ideas in this seminar that have
applicability in areas of interest to you. If you do attempt to apply ideas
from this seminar to particular ongoing work you are doing, I will be most
concerned about how well and how completely you have mastered the ideas you are
attempting to apply.��
����������� (4)
I will give very careful attention
to the coherency with which you present your ideas. Yes, I am concerned about
your ability to communicate your ideas in written form. I do you no service at
all by ignoring grammatical and stylistic matters.
����������� (5)
You should look upon this written work as something that you do for yourself,
not for me. It will simply demonstrate that you have attempted to acquire some uncommon understanding of a
probabilistic inferential issue that captures your interest.
����������� (6)
Please turn in your paper in hard copy rather than in electronic form. I would
rather spend the time reading carefully what you have done rather than waiting
for my slow computer to download your work and print it out.
����������� The
remaining 25% of your grade will be based upon some exercises and problems that
I will assign as we proceed. I expect to give you five such exercises during
the semester. Many of these exercises will involve probabilistic analyses of
various forms and combinations of evidence that appear in your text and in our
class discussions.
�
����������� ����������������������������������� A
"SEED" BIBLIOGRAPHY
����������� Following is a list of basic references
to works in each of the alternative systems of probabilistic reasoning we will
discuss. In addition, I have included one or more important references for each
system that are frequently cited but, with less frequency, actually read.
I. Views Based Upon The
Conventional [Pascalian] Calculus Of Probability.
����������� A. "Standard" Bayesianism
����������� Perhaps the most frequently cited
but infrequently read item on our list is the original paper by Thomas Bayes
that was communicated by Richard Price to the Royal Society Of London two years
after Bayes' death.
1)
An Essay Towards Solving A Problem In
The Doctrine Of Chances. By The Late Rev. Mr Bayes, F. R. S. Communicated
by Mr. Price in a letter to John Canton, A. M., F. R. S., Philosophical Transactions Of The Royal Society, pp 370-418, 1763.
2)
Dale, A. I. Most Honourable Remembrance:
The Life and Work of Thomas Bayes, Springer,� New York, NY., 2003.� This is the only extensive work on Bayes that
I know of. Bayes wrote several papers in mathematics in addition to the work
cited� in1) above. These papers are
included in Dale's book. So, if you want to find out more about Bayes, see this
book.
�����������
����������� There is now debate about whether or
not what has become known as Bayes' Rule should, in fact, be attributed to
Bayes. Here is a paper on the idea that others may have earlier tumbled to the
essence of Bayes' Rule.
3)
Stigler, S. M., Who Discovered Bayes's Theorem ? The American Statistician, November 1983, Vol. 37, No. 4, p
290 - 296.
����������� Here are some tutorials on the use
of Bayes' rule in probabilistic inference.
4)
von Winterfeldt, D., Edwards, W., Decision
Analysis And Behavioral Research, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1986, Chapters 5 and 6.
5)
Schum, D., Evidence And Inference For
The Intelligence Analyst [Two Volumes], Lanham, Md., University Press Of
America, 1987. Chapters 6, 7, and their supplements.
����������� There are now many references
relative to the use of Bayes' Rule in statistical
inference. Here are two places to start if you have interest in statistical
inference.
6)
Winkler, R., Introduction To Bayesian
Inference And Decision, New York, Holt, Rinehart, & Winston,
1972.
7)
O'Hagen, A., Probability: Methods And
Measurement, London, Chapman & Hall, 1988.
����������� Here are three works that, to
varying degrees, consider Bayes' rule as the normative standard for
probabilistic reasoning:
8)
Good, I. J. Good Thinking: The
Foundations of Probability and Its Applications. University of Minnesota
Press, Minneapolis. MN, 1983
9)
Earman, J., Bayes or Bust ?: A Critical
Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory, Bradford Books, MIT Press,
1992
10)
Howson, C., Urbach, P., Scientific
Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach, Open Court Press, 1989.
����������� Here are some works on the
application of Bayes' rule in complex "inferential networks"
11)
Pearl, J., Probabilistic Reasoning In
Intelligent Systems: Networks Of Plausible Inference, San Mateo
Calif., Morgan, Kaufman Publishers, 1988
12)
Schum, D., Evidence And Inference For
The Intelligence Analyst [Two Volumes], Lanham, Md., University Press Of
America, 1987. Particularly Chapters 4, and 8 through 12 and their supplements.
13)
Kadane, J., Schum, D. A Probabilistic
Analysis of the Sacco and Vanzetti Evidence. New York, Wiley, 1996 [A
Bayesian analyses of the evidence in a celebrated murder trial]
14)
Glymour, C. The Mind's Arrows: Bayes
Nets and Graphical Causal Models in Psychology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA,
2001
����������� We should note here that there is a
very large literature on various possible interpretations of numbers that
correspond to the standard or Pascalian calculus. Indeed, this is an entire
topic by itself. There are two useful summaries of alternative conceptions of a
Pascalian probability, they are:
15)� Fine, T., Theories Of Probability: An Examination Of Foundations, New York,
Academic Press, 1973
16)
Weatherford, R., Philosophical
Foundations of Probability Theory, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1982
����������� B. "Non-Standard"
Bayesianism.
����������� It has been claimed by several
Scandinavians [and one renegade Englishman] that we are frequently misguided in
the manner in which we apply Bayes' rule in drawing conclusions from evidence.
They have put together what is described as the evidentiary value model [EVM]. This model is basically
Bayesian but it rests upon a particular view of evidence and how it should be
used. I include EVM on this listing because it provides an interesting
transition to the next major view, the non-additive system of beliefs proposed
by Glenn Shafer. Over 20 years ago, I challenged the EVMers to show how this
system is in any way congenial to application in cascaded or hierarchical
inference; I am still waiting for a reply. Here is the major reference to EVM
research:
17)
Gardenfors, P., Hansson, B., Sahlin, N. E. [eds], Evidentiary Value: Philosophical, Judicial, And Psychological Aspects
Of A Theory. Lund, Sweden, C. W. K. Gleerups, 1983.
����������� There are several references in the
above work that are relevant to our next major view of probabilistic inference.
II. A Theory Of Nonadditive
Beliefs Based On Evidence.
����������� It is easily shown how probabilities
encountered in aleatory [games of
chance] and frequentistic
[statistical] contexts can be trapped within the Pascalian calculus. But what
about the array of epistemic contexts
in which numbers are used to grade the strength
of our beliefs about whether or not some event has happened, is happening,
or will happen ? In such contexts we often encounter singular, unique, or
nonreplicable events that can have no frequentistic interpretation. In
epistemic contexts many commonly-encountered credal or belief states cannot
easily be trapped within the bounds of the�
Pascalian system; it turns out that this has been known for centuries.
Our first reference here is a very useful and well-done treatise on the history
of the concept of probability. Discussed in this treatise are some of the
difficulties the Pascalian calculus has experienced in the trapping of these
credal states.
1)
Hacking, I., The Emergence Of
Probability, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1978.
����������� There are alternatives to the use of
Bayes' rule in the task of combining our beliefs based on some emerging body of
evidence; this has also been recognized for centuries. One mechanism for belief
combination has been termed "Dempster's rule"; this rule has roots in
much earlier work. In 1976 Glenn Shafer took Dempster's rule as the cornerstone
for a "new" system of probabilistic reasoning involving what he terms
a "belief function". We shall term this species of probabilistic
reasoning the "Shafer-Dempster" system.
����������� A. The Shafer-Dempster View.
����������� �Shafer was a student of Dempster's and has now
achieved a considerable measure of fame as a result of the following work:
2)� Shafer, G., A Mathematical Theory Of Evidence, Princeton, N.J., Princeton
University Press, 1976.
����������� Some of us believe this work is not
actually a theory of evidence but a theory of belief based upon evidence; form
your own opinion as we discuss his work and the work of others. Here is a
summary of recent thinking about the Shafer-Dempster system of belief
functions:
3)
Yager, R., Fedrizzi, M., Kacprzyk, J. Advances
in the Dempster-Shafer Theory of Evidence.
Ney York, John Wiley & Sons, 1994.
����������� Here are several often cited works
by Glenn Shafer that elaborate on the historical foundations of the
Shafer-Dempster view and that also are critical of any view in which Bayes'
rule is advocated as the "normative"
or "prescriptive" view of probabilistic reasoning.
4)
Shafer, G., Bayes's Two Arguments For The Rule Of Conditioning, The Annals Of Statistics, Vol.
10, No. 4, 1982.
5)
Shafer, G., Conditional Probability, International
Statistical Review, Vol. 53, 1985
6)Shafer,
G., The Combination Of Evidence, International
Journal Of Intelligent Systems, Vol. 1, 1986.
7)
Shafer, G., The Construction of Probability Argument, Boston University Law Review, Vol. 66, Nos, 3 & 4,
May/July, 1986.
8)
Shafer, G., Pearl, J., (eds), Readings
in Uncertain Reasoning, Morgan Kaufmann Publishers, 1989 [compares Bayes
with Shafer-Dempster. Formerly assigned as a text in this seminar].
����������� B. "Potential
Surprise": Another Nonadditive System.
����������� More than one person has been interested
in relationships between the concepts of probability
and possibility; one such person is
the British economist G. L. S. Shackle. In the following work Shackle proposed
a metric, called potential surprise,
for grading our beliefs about the possibility of events, something he believed
was not possible within the� Pascalian
calculus.
9)
Shackle, G. L. S., Decision, Order, And
Time In Human Affairs, Cambridge, 1969.�
����������� This system is still being
discussed, thanks to the efforts of the American philosopher Isaac Levi. Levi
claims this system to be quite general and sees in it some parallels with the
Shafer-Dempster system. In some quarters this system of reasoning is referred
to as the Levi-Shackle system of reasoning. Here are some further, more up to date
references to potential surprise.
10)
Levi., I., Decision And Revision:
Philosophical Essays On Knowledge And Value, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1984 [Chapter 14].
11)
Levi, I.,� The Enterprise Of Knowledge: An Essay On Knowledge, Credal Probability,
And Chance. Boston, MIT Press, 1983
III. Probability In Eliminative
and Variative Induction.
����������� In many contexts, science for
example, we subject our hypotheses to a testing process in which only the
fittest survive. In such tests evidence is used as a basis for eliminating hypotheses. As Professor L.
Jonathan Cohen will tell us in his book, a particular hypothesis seems to have
increasing probability or provability as it survives our best efforts to
invalidate it. We subject hypotheses to a variety of different
evidential tests; the more of these tests some hypothesis survives, the more
confidence we have in it. The key word here is variety; the survival of any hypothesis depends upon the extent to
which it holds up under different
conditions. Replication of test results is important but we cannot gather
support for some hypothesis simply by performing the same test over and over
again. Drawing upon the work of Sir Francis Bacon and John Stuart Mill,
Professor Cohen has given us a system of probability that is suited to what he
terms eliminative and variative inductive inference. In this
system of "Baconian" probabilistic reasoning, probabilities grade the
extent to which some hypothesis survives an eliminative testing process, The
"weight" of evidence, in Baconian terms, is related to the number of evidential tests we perform
and to the extent to which our tests cover variables relevant in discriminating
among the hypotheses we consider. Cohen's system is the only system that
specifically grades the completeness or
the sufficiency of our evidence. How likely we view some hypothesis depends
upon how many relevant questions concerning our hypotheses that our existing
evidence does not answer.
����������� The first reference is to Cohen's
work on developing means for grading the inductive
support that evidence provides in the eliminative testing process Cohen
describes.
1)
Cohen, L. J., The Implications Of
Induction, London, Methuen & Co. Ltd., 1970.
����������� Cohen certainly acknowledges that
there is room for more than one view of probabilistic reasoning. Cohen's
"polycriterial" account of probability is given in the following
three references, the second of which can probably be termed his major work.
2)
Cohen. L. J., Probability: The One And The Many, Proceedings Of The British Academy, V ol. LXI, 1975.
3)
Cohen. L. J., The Probable And The
Provable, Oxford, The Clarendon Press, 1977.
4)
Cohen, L. J., An Introduction to the
Philosophy of Induction and Probability, Oxford University Press, 1989. I
used to require every student to read this work; it is truly outstanding.
Unfortunately, it is now out of print.
����������� Here are several other of Cohen's
works that are of particular importance to anyone seeking to understand the
full dimensions of Cohen's views.
5)
Cohen, L. J., Bayesianism Versus Baconianism In The Evaluation Of Medical
Diagnosis. British Journal For The
Philosophy Of Science, Vol. 31, 1980.
6)
Cohen, L. J., Twelve Questions About Keynes's Conception Of Weight, British Journal For The Philosophy Of
Science, Vol. 37, 1985.
7)
Cohen, L. J., Hesse, M., The
Applications Of Inductive Logic, Oxford, The Clarendon Press, 1980.
8)
Cohen, L. J., The Dialogue Of Reason,
Oxford, The Clarendon Press, 1986.
����������� Here are three references in which
Cohen's Baconian system is discussed and compared with other views.
9)
Schum, D., A Review Of A Case Against Blaise Pascal And His Heirs, University Of Michigan Law Review, Vol.
77, No. 3, 1979.
10)
Schum, D., Probability And The Processes Of Discovery, Proof, And Choice. Boston University Law Review, Vol. 66.,
Nos. 3 & 4, May/July 1986.
11)
Schum, D., Jonathan Cohen And Thomas Bayes On The Analysis Of Chains Of
Reasoning. In: Rationality And
Reasoning: Essays In Honor Of L. Jonathan Cohen [eds. Eells, E.,
Maruszewski, T.] Amsterdam, Rodopi, 1991.
IV. Imprecision, Fuzzy
Probabilities, And Possibilities.
����������� The Pascalian system of probability
is rooted in a system of two-valued logic; a statement is either true or false
or a particular element is either in some subset or it isn't. In 1965 Professor
Lotfi Zadeh argued that our inferences and decisions are often based upon
information that is imprecise or
ambiguous and for which this two-valued logic is inappropriate. He coined
the term "fuzzy sets" to describe collections of elements with
indistinct, imprecise, or "elastic" boundaries. Zadeh has argued that
a different calculus is necessary to represent reasoning based upon fuzzy
information. His early work has generated enormous enthusiasm and there are now
well over 15,000 papers, books, and other materials that have been published on
fuzzy matters since 1965, the year in which Zadeh's work on fuzzy sets saw the
light of day.
1)
Zadeh, L., "Fuzzy Sets", Information
And Control, Vol. 8, 1965.
����������� Zadeh and his now enormous
international body of followers have published papers on the application of
fuzzy sets in an array of inferential and decisional contexts. The best single
collection of Zadeh's papers is found in the following.
2)
Yager, R., Ovchinnikov, S., Tong, R., Nguyen, H., Fuzzy Sets And Applications: Selected Papers By L. A. Zadeh, New
York, Wiley & Sons, 1987.
����������� Here are several fairly current
works that may be regarded as tutorial regarding fuzzy sets and systems.
3)
Klir, G., Folger, T., Fuzzy Sets,
Uncertainty, and Information, Prentice Hall, 1988
4)
McNeill, D., Freiberger, P., Fuzzy Logic,
Simon & Schuster, 1993
5)Kosko,
B., Fuzzy Thinking: The New Science of
Fuzzy Logic, Hyperion, 1993. This is an absorbing (but frequently
irritating) work by the leading spear-carrier of fuzzy reasoning.
����������� The following work is critical of
the idea that fuzzy logic actually extends classical logic.
6)
Haack, S. Deviant Logic, Fuzzy Logic:
Beyond the Formalism. University of Chicago Press, 1996.��
V. Probabilistic Inference And
Its Role In Decisions
����������� As noted in your syllabus, we should
give attention to inferential activity in the following two contexts. In many
situations, various areas of science for example, inferential activity is
simply part of the process of knowledge-acquisition. However, in other
situations such as in law, medicine, intelligence analysis, and so on,
inferential activity is embedded in the further process of choice. In all of
these other situations, assessments of probability have somehow to be combined
with assessments of the value of consequences that occur to us when we
contemplate various choices in the face of uncertainty. There is a substantial
literature on the combination of inferential and value-related ingredients in
choice under uncertainty. Two quite different views of this process of
combination are found in the following three references.
1)
von Winterfeldt, D., Edwards, W., Decision
Analysis And Behavioral Research, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1986.� [See Chapters 1, 2, 3]
2)
Lindley, D., Making Decisions, [2nd
ed], London, Wiley & Sons, 1985.
3)
Shafer. G., Savage Revisited, Statistical
Science, Vol. 1, No. 4., 1986.
LAST BUT NOT LEAST, WHERE TO
FIND YOUR INSTRUCTOR
����������� I usually lurk in the vicinity of
Room 111-A, Science & Technology Bldg. II; my office phone is 703-993-1694.
If I am not in my office, I am almost certainly at home: 2219 Chestertown Dr.,
Vienna, Va. My home phone is: 703-698-9515. Please do not hesitate to contact
me at any of these locations; come by my office any time the mood suits, you
are always welcome. If all else fails, or if you simply prefer electronic mail,
my home e-mail address is: <[email protected]>. My GMU e-mail
system does not work properly. I will do all I can to make this seminar useful
and enjoyable for you.
�����������